Help
Index

 Maarten Maartensz:    Philosophical Dictionary | Filosofisch Woordenboek                      

 I - Infinity

 

Infinity: What has no end, no boundary, no limit.

The infinite or infinity has been the subject of much speculation in philosophy and mathematics, and also in theology, where it has been widely considered to be one of God's attributes.

The definition I proposed is like the Greek, who used the term 'to apeiron' for it - the boundless - and speculated quite a lot about it.

It is quite easy to imagine that one can take one more step, or divide something one more time, and never stop doing this. Then what? Where does it end? Can it end? Can it fail to end? How does one know? Aristotle has an interesting and subtle discussion, but no really precise analysis, and no mathematics of infinity.

By far the most precise analysis of the concept of infinity, certainly mathematically speaking, was first made by Georg Cantor, who also developed set theory to provide an analysis of it.

A set-theoretical definition of an infinite set is: A set which has a proper subset that is as large as the set itself. A proper subset of a set is a subset of a set that lacks at least one element that is in the set. The reason for the definition may be presented as follows (using a sort of argument Galileo also knew):

           1   2   3   4   5  ... n ... and so on

           2   4   6   8  10 .. 2n ... and so on

The first line is the beginning of a full listing of the natural numbers; the second line is the beginning of a full listing of the even natural numbers. Now it is clear that for any number in the first list, there corresponds precisely one double of it in the second list, and to every number in the second list, there corresponds precisely one half of it in the first list, and indeed one can combine both into one list of pairs thus:

          (1,2) (2,4) (3,6) ... (n, 2n) ... and so on

Now, if one supposes that two sets have the same number iff there is a 1-1 correspondence between them, then the argument just given strongly suggests there are precisely as many natural numbers as there are even natural numbers - supposing that either collection indeed has a totality, that can be meaningfully said to have a number, which is what Cantor supposed.

This shows, accordingly, on those Cantorian assumptions, also a way in which infinite sets - as defined - differ from finite sets, for the number of a proper subset of a finite set is always smaller than the number of the set it is a proper subset of.

And to conclude the argument: Clearly, the even natural numbers are a proper subset of the natural numbers, in the sense that each even natural number is a natural number, whereas some natural numbers - all the odd ones, indeed - are not among the even natural numbers.

Consequently, at least plausibly, the natural numbers are an infinite set, for it contains a proper subset that has precisely as many numbers as it, and so is as large as it. (The reader should note that the weakest point of the above argument is the assumption that an infinite set has a totality, that has a number.)

All of this was meant to illustrate the sort of reasoning that led Cantor to his set-theoretical definition of infinity, but it should be remarked that in the case of the natural numbers one can do without: These are also infinite in sense that there is no largest (finite) natural number, since one always can get another one that is still larger by adding 1 to the hitherto largest. And this is the sense of limitlessness the Greeks already knew and pondered. Here it is not assumed that what is limitless has a totality and a number.

Cantor was a mathematician, and part of his reasons (though not all, since he also had philosophical and theological concerns) was to provide a clear and cogent foundation for the many arguments in mathematics that somehow involve the notion of the infinite, namely in the calculus (differential and integral); in geometry (projective, especially); with series, like 1/2, 1/4, ... , 1/2n and their sums and convergences (the series just given intuitively sums to 1 and converges towards 0, all "in the limit", "after an infinity of terms" - (*)); and indeed with the natural and real numbers, of which there seem to be infinitely many, and about which Cantor had an ingenious argument to prove that even so there are more real numbers than there are natural numbers.

A good introduction to the many problems involved in the notion is A.W. Moore's "The Infinite", that concerns both the mathematical and the philosophical notions of the infinite, has mostly clear explanations, and defends a kind of finitism.

Indeed, one good argument to show that Cantorian infinities are a bit difficult to swallow intuitively is that by the axiom of the power set of standard set theory there always is a power set of any given set, which by an argument of Cantor must always be greater than the set itself. Hence there are infinities upon infinities - which, for one thing, is more than is needed for classical mathematics, for that can do with such infinities as are involved in the natural and real numbers, that are - or seem to be - the smallest infinities in the Cantorian hierarchy of infinities, implied by the power set axiom.

A good introduction to how infinity is dealt with in standard mathematics for the calculus and the theory of functions, mostly without set theory, is Konrad Knopp's "Infinite sequences and series". Any good introduction to set theory  shows how infinities are reckoned with there. Any calculus text presumes some theory of infinity, though usually this is not clearly and fully articulated in such texts (in which this may not be necessary either).


(*) To show the sort of ordinary mathematical reasoning with or around infinities, here are proofs of the statements that the infinite series 1/2, 1/4, ... , 1/2n, ....  sums to 1 and converges towards 0:

A. Suppose 1/2 + 1/4 + ... + 1/2+ .... ad infinitum has a sum. Call it S. Then we have 1/2 + 1/4 + ... + 1/2+ .... = S. Multiply all terms of this equation by 2 (and suppose you can do this an infinity of times). The result must be 1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + ... + 1/2 + .... = 2S which is to say 1+S=2S which is to say S=1. Qed.

B. Let me have all of 1/2, 1/4, ... ,1/2n, .... ad infinitum. Now if anyone chooses any small non-zero difference or distance, as small as he pleases, from 0, then I can produce a number from the series which is even smaller. So I can approximate 0 as closely as I wish, or he wishes, and within any arbitrarily assigned small distance. Qed.

One other reason for this footnote is to show the sort of arguments ordinary mathematicians used. Both arguments can be found in Leibniz, in the 17th C, when founding the calculus, if not precisely in these terms.

It was this sort of reasoning Cantor wanted to make really precise, and for this reason he found or created the foundations of set theory and indeed introduced the concept set.

 


See also: Powerset, Set theory


Literatuur:

Benacerraf & Putnam, Cantor, Halmos, Moore, Russell, Suppes

 Original: Aug 25, 2004                                                Last edited: 24 January 2012.   Top